An Eclectic Set of Academic Musings-

An Eclectic Set of Academic Musings-

Friday, June 21, 2013

I Was Just Walking Down The Street One Day, When I Tripped, and Fell into Love!; Merton, Sartre, and de Beauvior Criticize The Avoidance of Existential Responsibility


     Merton, Sartre, and de Beauvior are three existential philosophers who criticize our social tendency to avoid taking existential responsibility at all costs. Merton begins this criticism with a scathing attack on the very language we use to describe love. Merton exposes the phase, “I fell in love” as complete bullshit. The implications of such an utterance are clear, love is described like and accident, as if you had tripped on something and tumbled into a foreign world. Falling in love is described as if the lover was just walking down the street one day, minding her own business, and then BAM! Love jumps out from behind a fire hydrant and smacks you in the face with a frying pan. Good god, that couldn’t have been your fault.  
This phrase “falling in love” views love as a choice you didn’t get to make. It paints love as an assault, a rampage, a kidnapping. We allow our language to carry the weight of our existential responsibility so we don’t have to take ownership of our feelings. A lack of personal responsibility is engrained in the very description of love. Interestingly, this manipulation of language as a means of avoidance of culpability extends from the initiation of love, into the experience of it. Have you ever heard the Beyonce song, Crazy in Love ? In the chorus she croons a common phrase: Im crazy in love. This choice of language has the same motives as ‘falling in love’. By allowing love to appear as a consuming, controlling force, we eliminate the responsibility for our actions within a loving relationship. We talk about the lover as if he were a drug addict- so overwhelmed with foreign influence that he has gone completely mad- able to see his actions but helpless to stop them.
While Merton thinks we avoid responsibility by allowing language to carry the weight, de Beauvior claims that women have figured out unique ways to avoid such, by allowing their men to carry the weight. de Beauvior claims that women are first conditioned into an androcentric world- they are taught to believe men are more capable than themselves. As they become adults, and move away from the parents who controlled their liberty, they face the overwhelming fear of ‘taking the reins’ of their lives. Wracked with anxiety, these women find means of avoiding existential responsibility in the social convention of love. They gravitate towards the strong, almost divine, male figure they have been raised to revere. Women crave male authority to shield them from their own liberty. To accomplish this, women tuck away their liberty and self-identity behind the husband figure. Women assume the identity of their men (The first lady, Mrs. Dr. Johnson, the army wife, the list goes on). This kind of woman abandons her hobbies and picks up those of her husband. She does not formulate ideas; she simply repeats those that her husband told her. She has no political opinions outside of her husband, nor interests, nor value, nor anything at all for that matter. She exists entirely within him. And doesn’t that just sound lovely. How relaxing to never have to make any bothersome choices like what you believe or who you are.
To a modern and educated woman this prospect is repulsive and disgusting. But to the existentially anxious woman, it’s far better than taking responsibility. Thus, these women accept their oppression in order to remain warm and cozy behind their man, and only just out of reach of liberty’s influence.  Woman live vicariously through their husbands, even their love for themselves comes through his eyes. In this way, she can attribute her every action and behavior to her husband’s decisions. Her beliefs, her religion, her mood, her life, all become his responsibility.
Finally, Sartre chimes in and states his belief that not just women, but every human, longs to dump their responsibility onto the shoulders of other people. Sartre claims that we are desperate to have our own self-identity defined by the recognition of others.  Sartre argues that the only true constraint of our radical freedoms (and therefore existential responsibility) comes from the radical freedoms of those around us. We desperately try to skirt our own freedom, by assuming the opinions others have of us. Sartre says we want to be judged by others, we want the recognition of another to define how we see ourselves. In this way, we are able to see ourselves through the eyes of another, but are never forced to take responsibility for the creation of our identity- its been done for us. For example, in Sartre’s critical play No Exit, the character Garcin is desperate to hear Inez tell him he is courageous. He believes that if a woman whom he considers to be radically free, tells him he is courageous, then he will be. However, when given the opportunity to make a radical choice to define himself as courageous, he is too afraid to claim it. Garcin would prefer to live within the unflattering recognition of another person, than to live with a self-conception of his identity and take responsibility for his liberty.
These three authors attack various conventions (mainly love) that enable us to ‘unload’ responsibility for ourselves.  Certainly, all three would agree that conventions are the paradise of the weak- a beautiful world of familiar, pre-defined roles we can slip ourselves right into, with no explanations needed.  There is no need to think or develop one’s own motivations. No need to define yourself- everyone has done it for you; they heard that story before.  

No comments:

Post a Comment